STINA TEILMANN AND N55 EXCHANGING


Stina Teilmann is a Ph.D. candidate researching on literary and artistic property rights in France and Great Britain.
The exchange is based on an e-mail conversation that took place between February 2002 and May 2003, partly during N55�s residency in Los Angeles, USA.


RN55:
Thanks for your visit. Here are some exerpts from About ownership of knowledge and About ownership of land, by N55 as promised. Read also ART AND REALITY.

Patents- ownership of objective knowledge:
Science is about making right assertions. Right assertions represent objective knowledge. Objective knowledge is something which can�t be denied meaningfully if we want to talk rationally together. Objective knowledge can be knowledge about facts: at four o�clock they sat down and did this, or this mountain is 3000 meters high. Objective knowledge can also be knowledge about logical relations. To take a patent on, for example, knowledge about the human genome or a new type of medicine is to claim ownership of objective knowledge. This means that some persons claim the ownership of logical relations and knowledge about facts. This ownership means that other persons must pay to use objective knowledge, or that other persons are not allowed at all to use it. If we claim a patent to objective knowledge, we also say that some persons can use logical relations and facts and some can not: Here we have a person, who should be treated as a person and therefore as having rights, but this person is not allowed to use logical relations or knowledge about facts. It does not make sense to claim ownership of objective knowledge. If we try to defend ownership of objective knowledge using language in a rational way it goes wrong. The only way to defend ownership of objective knowledge is to use power and force. No persons have more rights to use logical relations or knowledge about facts than other persons, but concentrations of power use force to maintain the illusion of ownership of objective knowledge.

Ownership of land:
It is a habitual conception that ownership of land is acceptable. Most societies are characterized by the convention of ownership. But if we claim the ownership of land, we also say that we have more rights to parts of the surface of the earth than other persons have. We know that persons should be treated as persons and therefore as having rights. If we say here is a person who has rights, but this person has no right to stay on the surface of the earth, it does not make sense. If one does not accept that persons have the right to stay on the surface of the earth, it makes no sense to talk about rights at all. If we try to defend ownership of land using language in a rational way it goes wrong. The only way to defend ownership is to use power and force. No persons have more rights to land than other persons, but concentrations of power use force to maintain the illusion of ownership of land.

ST:
I am writing from Churchill College, Cambridge, where I am spending the autumn semester, in order to find material about copyright and images for my thesis. At the moment I am looking into how the Diana, Princess of Wales Memorial Trust is using trademarks to control the image and the signature of the princess on all sorts of things: dolls, postcards, porcelain, flowers, souvenirs etcetera. The trust uses trade marking because Great Britain barely has privacy rights and has no publicity rights, as many states in the U.S. do. For example Washington State, where celebrities have the exclusive rights to their own image until seventy years after their deaths and ordinary people until ten years after. (How do you distinguish by the way?) I am also looking at digitalized pictures. Museums and picture archives are into a new business: copyrighting digital pictures of artworks, which in themselves are too old to be in copyright. There is a tendency that older art and literature, that otherwise would belong to the public domain, in this way is brought under renewed copyright. In literature, "authentic" and "revised" versions of popular authors� works start to appear. The publisher claims renewed copyright, even though the author died seventy years ago or more. And in some of these publications, there is a warning in the colophon to all scholars that citations are only allowed by permission of the holder of the new right: author�s Estate, the heirs, the publisher or editor of the new text.

I brought your three text pieces (About Ownership of Land, About Ownership of Knowledge, and Art an Reality) with me to England and I have had the intention of writing you for a long time. I find what you are saying of tremendous importance. Recently, I read that intellectual property typically comprises more than 5% of a Western national economy. And ever more is regarded as intellectual property these days. There was a lawsuit in England where a person brought his friends to court for "stealing" an idea for a discotheque with more floors and several bars and so on (how original...). Another famous trial revolved around a celebrity couple that sued a person for selling pictures of their wedding to the press.1 The couple claimed the exclusive rights to the profits from pictures taken at the party. I find that people increasingly demand ownership over things that are just trivial and common property, over what cannot be monopolized at all. Copyright laws have become something of a trash bin for the urge to possess and control knowledge and ideas. It has been forgotten that the original purpose of copyright in the 18th century was to encourage the dissemination of art and new knowledge. Furthermore people seem no longer to question the idea of ownership of intangibles. Some regard intellectual property rights as natural givens. It is not. It is a modern invention. There may be many good reasons to grant copyright and patents: it is often argued that it encourages creativity and inventiveness. But then why not try to establish if this is true? This empirical ambition does not appeal much to legislators however. Instead, because there is such a strong pressure to define and justify copyright, patents and trade marks as property all possible rhetorical means are made use of. And legal debate drowns in analogies. The favorite analogy of intellectual property law, inspired by the philosopher John Locke (1632-1704), is that "the one who has sown, also has the right to harvest."2 Locke�s idea was that:

"[t]hough the earth and all inferior creatures be common to all men, yet every man has a property in his own person; this nobody has any right to but himself. The labour of his body and the work of his hands we may say are properly his. Whatsoever, then, he removes out of the state that nature has provided and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property. It being by him removed from the common state nature placed it in, it hath by this labour something annexed to it that excludes the common right of other men."3

This way of reasoning by analogy and farming metaphors has become so integrated in our thinking that it is hardly questioned any more. And it is as if all discussion stops here. I would like to ask if copyright and patents must come under property law and not, for instance, under contract law?

Another concern I have in relation to intellectual property law is that lawyers always say that "legal wording is not what the general reader of English is used to". Does that immunize them against external criticism, and exempt the law of the need of a rationale for copyright in plain English? Ideas and knowledge have a greater potential to be used by many persons at the same time than most physical things. And with the contemporary technology of dissemination, we are close to the Enlightenment�s ideal of free access to knowledge. But as you say, the rights of some soon become the restrictions of others. Intellectual property rights need our consideration; do they become a violation of the rights of the majority?

I have the following reflections: since intellectual property rights cannot be justified logically, their aims and effects must always be made explicit. And the effects must not work against the purposes. For example copyright must not be used by jealous heirs to prevent the publishing of manuscripts to which they have inherited the copyright. That is possible today. Nor should the harmonizing of the intellectual property legislation within the European union have as its result that British artists cannot reuse material to which they have sold the copyright. This may be happening now. According to British law, artists and authors can sell their copyright outright, while a certain clause secures them the right to reuse their own material. If this clause gets harmonized away, a British author risks losing, for example, the right to reuse her or his own novel character. Neither should it be forgotten that although a published work is not in the public domain, it still is in the public sphere. One cannot expect to have the full control over something which is addressed to a large audience. It seems for instance absurd to want to forbid links to homepages which are already publicly accessible. With all this in mind, I ask myself whether it would not be more meaningful to have privileges to land and knowledge, instead of ownership to it Enough law for now. Only, law has such an immense influence on our lives � perhaps it is reckless to leave it to lawyers alone?

N55:
It was very interesting to hear about your investigations. The convention that one has the right to buy ownership is quite uncontested. Copyright to knowledge is a cultural disease, which has a lot to do with the economic force we are subjected to. And that in western culture, the profit motive is in high esteem, often in the guise of other considerations, like the one that a researcher-author-inventor should be allowed to harvest the honor and the fruits of his work and investments, as you mention. That monetary wealth is a good to strive for is such a deeply rooted concept that it becomes incredibly difficult to imagine that things could be otherwise. This concept is nurtured by the existence of very deep poverty and the fear that it should hit one self, which is an absolute possibility in a country without social security. Fear is an important driving force in the USA. It becomes increasingly important to avoid similar conditions in Scandinavia (we are getting there). The USA is of course the best example of a culture which has gone berserk with regard to profit. A trip out on the street tells you that this is how reality is defined here. It seems crazy to stand on the pavement between a homeless person and a shop selling expensive antiquated furniture and at the same time assert that it should or could be different. The differences are so graphic as if they had been created by natural forces. It is not surprising that a society like this encourages opportunism and pragmatism and ridicules and marginalizes everybody who tries to maintain that things can be done in a different way. Neither is it surprising that many political activists concentrate on single cases like welfare of prisoners or recycling- because the superior force is so massive.

Ownership is a foundation stone in capitalist thinking and is based on the notion that fundamental resources are not common, but commodities that can be speculated in like other commodities. If society is defined as a competition and a struggle between everybody, the most obvious solution is that people have to acquire what they need through force and competition. If we define it otherwise, we have other options. Common property (in modern time) has normally been linked with a strong concentration of power, a socialist state, which puts forward another ideology than the capitalist state. That is a huge problem, which is connected to the fact that we live in nation states and large political entities that present themselves through models and ideologies. We have very little experience in organizing smaller concentrations of power, and that is probably why every assertion that we should try to organize smaller concentrations of power, are rejected as unrealistic With regards to intellectual property: this is significant not only to art and literature but also in relation to patents. This is particularly scary in a global context because legislation in the rich areas of the earth stand together in denying poorer countries access to cheap medicine, for example. Another example is food production: Farmers in order to be competitive have to use modified seed and pesticides designed by "life science" companies, and this rapidly bars access to other types of seed and other forms of production. A group of scientists in Norway is among those who warn against the unrestrained use of genetically modified organisms; they say that the possible harmful effects are about as well documented as those of Thalidomide or DDT when they entered the markets in the 50s and 60s. They also say that independent research facilities and independent institutions start becoming a sparse "commodity". Because so many researchers are sponsored (bought) or work for companies that want to produce saleable products as soon as possible, it could become big business to be able to offer independent research. Patenting basic things like food and medicine is legitimized by arguments that the companies need to get their investments back, and the patents are used to prevent others from getting access to the same knowledge. By ignoring that there is no logical foundation for ownership, one looks away from our only possibilities to distinguish between right and wrong. Thereafter, the game is free for social conventions and power games. By taking language seriously and respecting that which we cannot disagree about, logic, we have the possibility to find ways of organizing which are not the results of ideological concepts or power interests. Unfortunately, it doesn�t seem logic is what those in power are concerned the most with at the moment.
In his book "Slide Mountain, or The Folly of Owning Nature",4 Theodore Steinberg relates some entertaining examples from trials in the USA; they are all concerning the question of whether and to what extent people can own nature. There are conflicts about soil that remain after a river changed it�s course, about "weather modification companies" that was a promising enterprise in the 60s (which now seems to reappear), that by sprinkling silver iodide over clouds could make them snow or rain, (which led to accusations that these companies had caused drought elsewhere) about who owns the air over a plot of land and the water under and so on. The author also describes how pre-capitalist thinking in Europe imagined the right to own land: A peasant in feudalism could not own land, but he could have rights in land; that means, a kind of right to be there and to use it, that was telling more of the social relations to others who also had rights in the land (the nobility, the monarch). But the point seems to be that where ownership of land previously was a way to describe social relations, and the use of things, in capitalism it signifies a clear right to something, which is no different from the way that private ownership of immovable things was accepted. As soon as land had been accepted as a commodity, it was less difficult to imagine that for example air and water could be so. Now if you say that houses and shoes can be owned just as little as land, water and air, we also say that our whole exchange of commodities is built on the construction that one can have an exclusive right to things that have been exchanged for that which corresponds to the thing�s value in money. You don�t have to enter a definite social relation in order to get the thing.
Perhaps you know about the chair we made, DYNAMIC CHAIR, it contained an invention: the seat rests on a sphere, making the seat moveable. This principle could be patented, but we refrained from it. This was partly because after looking into the patent system, we found that it could only protect you from copying if you had the means to take out a patent in all countries, and partly because it got us into some considerations about the wrong in keeping other persons away from knowledge that exists in the world. What we wanted to protect ourselves against was that people could copy it and profit on something that was never meant as a commodity. By publishing the chair and its construction principle, we made it possible for others to use the principle, and at the same time ensured that no one else could claim patent rights to the principle that would enable them to market and sell it. During the last years we have made some copies of the chair and this has evolved into an experiment with things, circulation and significance. People who want it pay a price that corresponds to how much time, material and development went into it. And when they take over the chair they promise that they will not resell it or use it for any kind of speculation in art objects. They can�t just buy it, and then decide totally over it. A specific relationship to other persons follows. It is suggested that they respect the context the chair was thought into.
LAND functions in some ways similar to this; the formal owners abandon their exclusive ownership to the land so anybody can stay there and use it. Nobody can decide exclusively over the land, but have to enter a relation to other persons if they want to use it In relation to what you wrote, we wonder about a couple of things. What is the difference between public domain and public sphere? How should one define the difference between privileges to land and knowledge, and ownership of land and knowledge?

ST:
I think the difference between the public domain and the public sphere is forced. The public domain is a term used in law. It consists of what cannot be protected as literary or artistic property, what has fallen out of copyright and what, for some reason, has not been copyrighted. Perhaps the public domain is really negatively defined: it consists of what is left over when exclusive rights have been claimed. The public sphere is what we all contribute to, what no one can monopolize. I maintain that the division between the public domain and the public sphere is forced because everything, when it is published, is made public, inevitably enters the public sphere. In spite of this, some things are artificially held back from the public domain until the end of a term of, for example, copyright.

A preliminary definition of a right is that to which a person has a just and lawful claim or that which is recognized by law, violation of which being a legal wrong. Rights may derive from natural law (the underlying basis of all law with its idea of perfect justice). A privilege is defined by the Oxford English Dictionary as "a grant to an individual, corporation, community, or place, of special rights to immunities, sometimes to the prejudice of the general right; a franchise, monopoly, patent; specifically the sole right of printing or publishing a book or the like." A privilege is a temporary right, not deriving from natural law; it is founded in society. When the first laws on literary and artistic property were passed in the eighteenth century it was intensely disputed whether copyright was to be recognized as a right or as a privilege. The distinction has great implications to intellectual property law. And it is most interesting in relation to the mentioned pre-capitalist forms of rights to land.

Your description of rights as the entry into a social relation pierces right through what has puzzled me recently about �ownership�: namely, the difference between a "title" and a "right" to something. How is ownership a right? Title is a person�s right of ownership of land. Right, I should say, is a right to act in relation to something. Now, I found this fascinating analysis in the English case Donaldon v. Beckett (1774). It was held that:

"Incorporeal property is of two sorts: 1st, It is a right relating to some substance, as a right to take the profits of land, without having the possession of the land or a title to it. 2dly, It is a right to exercise some faculty, or to do some particular thing for profit. The perception of the profits, is a taking of some substance or corporeal property; and hence the incorporeal right is metaphorically called property."5

I wonder if one might say that property, in the beginning, was mainly a right to particular acts, for instance to cultivate land, the right being more of a social agreement.6 Only later did property and ownership develop into its present form: one person�s absolute power over something, related social relations totally dictated by this person�s title to the thing. This gives us two kinds of ownership (1) title to land, or (2) a right to profit from it, the former constituting our usual way of understanding ownership. I speculate, then, whether a collective oblivion has spread. We forget that it is possible for ownership to be of the second kind, that ownership may be defined as the exclusive right to certain acts in relation to, for example, land while not implying title to it and supreme power over it.

N55:
Only because one has the opportunity to buy a piece of land, it doesn�t imply one has the right A recent example from a village in France where a piece of land is now part of LAND: The village, using its possibilities for pre-emption, bought this piece of land. A private person has brought them to court for this, because he claims he should have been to granted the right to buy the land. The interesting thing is that this man wants to buy the land only to abandon it; he wants to let it turn to wilderness as he has done with all the other land he has bought up during his 30 years of presence in the area. The village, on the other hand, wants to use this land for cultural purposes, a sculpture park. This person is an advocate for wilderness and animals, always in conflict with the villagers who fear brushfires because of the lack of maintenance. The area has been occupied by humans for 50,000 years, while human activity has dominated and shaped the landscape, so surely any "natural state" is an idealized construction. He uses his legal possibilities to enforce upon the collectivity of the village a landscape which they do not want and which poses a danger to them At the time of writing the case is not settled and in the meantime, the plot is part of LAND and subject to anything the villagers and others, animals included, want to do there.

ST:
That is interesting. This self-styled back-to-nature man seeks ownership not as a means to profit from the land but to obtain absolute power over it. This reminds me of the continuation of the Locke passage from before. Locke modifies his definition of ownership by saying that although "this labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer, no man but he can have a right to what is once joined to" it is only as long as "there is enough and as good left in common for others."(15) There are limits as to how much one man can make his own. Enough should always be left for others. And a further and often ignored restriction by Locke is that what is taken from the common state must not go to waste. Thus, one man can own only "[a]s much as any one can make use of to any advantage of life before it spoils, so much he may by his labour fix a property in; whatever is beyond this is more than his share, and belongs to others. Nothing was made by God for man to spoil or destroy."(17) In Locke�s definition only labour justifies a right of ownership and this puts a natural limit to concentrations of power ownership and to ownership as a device for control.

N55:
Yes, but labour in the 16th century and labour now are very different things if we speak of agricultural work At the beginning of English settlement in North America, the system of landownership known from feudal Europe was enforced there. Huge estates were parceled out to a few people who also possessed the political power. Other people, if they wanted other possibilities than being servants to the landlords and the merchants in the cities, were forced westwards to get land. In this way, they could also serve as a buffer against the Indians. After the revolution, during which the ties to the English monarchy were severed, political influence remained with landholders and only people who owned property were allowed to vote. This is an example of how ownership is connected to concentrations of power. Today the connections seem more blurred, as production is more complex. However, one can still discern the relation to political influence when one looks at who owns what. The basic needs of persons (food, shelter, clothing, etc.) are the same as ever; in addition, we have got a lot of created needs (transportation, communication, all the different things we eat and drink, entertainment, education, etc.) at which production is directed. When you seek to cover any one of these needs you deal with different concentrations of power. The companies are either state or privately owned. The rights to cultivate, fish, build, establish communication lines and so on depend on various forms of ownership of land, buildings, patents, licenses and more. So the question of ownership cannot be treated separately from other issues to which it is related. Actually, in most instances, ownership is the precondition for the various kinds of production: first one secures the ownership of land, copyright, and so on, and then one starts to produce goods, print books, etc. It is clear that property law and copyright as the right to profit is instrumental to much of the kind of production we are faced with daily.

ST:
Still, I think it�s not so much the granting of (temporary) rights to profit from something as the possibility of keeping title � that is absolute power over something � which creates concentrations of power. This is why I try to make out the distinction between privilege and title. Interested in intangible property as I am I want to sort out the implications of the distinction for intellectual property rights. At the time when intellectual property was invented the advocates for property rights (rather than privileges) believed that the holder of a copyright had something analogous to title to his or her work. This would have included a perpetual dominion over it. Yet as argued in the analysis of incorporeal property in Donaldson v. Beckett (the decision actually put an end to perpetual common law copyright in Britain) copyright � the exclusive right to print copies as it were � by definition is the right to take profit but without title. There is no thing to which one can have title. Knowledge is not a thing. Property, in this case, can only be a metaphor and copyright can only be a privilege. I think that we are gradually forgetting that an exclusive right to print is not necessarily identical with title to something and unrestrained control over it.

N55:
You know one should not be too blue-eyed. These producers and concentrations of power (in various degrees and shapes) couldn�t care less whether their ownership is logical or not. What means something to them is that the law secures their interests. What we have to find out is whether it also secures our rights as persons. Therefore, although it is interesting to look into the different details and distinctions in lawmaking, as long as it serves the same ends: securing rights to profit, it doesn�t make much of a difference whether it is called rights or privileges (at least you will have to convince me of that). If someone has exclusive rights to profit, but apart from that will not prevent others from accessing the property whether it is knowledge or land, what is the difference? I am allowed to read the book, but not to copy it. I am allowed to step on the land, but not to cultivate it. I am allowed to visit a building, but not to stay there. I am allowed to read the code of a gene but can�t prevent it from entering my food. The profit motive is the uncontested assumption that allows private ownership to exist. So we have to ask: is it not a reduction of persons to say that the main motivation for their actions should be the wish to profit? If there were no other wishes connected with work, publishing something, research, than the wish to profit, would we then do it? To say that all that compels people to go on producing stuff is the desire to make money and to make a social and material advancement in relation to others is a simplification that is typical of the way ideologies explain human behavior. The more reality is defined in a certain way, the more we start to behave accordingly out of fear and out of obedience to social conventions and habitual ways of thinking. To describe persons as beings that seek to profit from their surroundings is to reduce persons to something definite. This is not compatible with respecting persons and their rights.
Rather we have to say that profiting is one of the things persons do. The Yaruk tribe who lived in the California area had something equivalent to private ownership of land and are described as being obsessed with money (their money was made of dentalium shells) and used money to settle every dispute. To accumulate a lot of money was regarded as a good thing, where in other societies money was either unheard of, or regarded as inferior. It is an example of how social conventions foster certain kinds of behavior. The Inuit had no money or private ownership of land. The problem is that once a social convention that fosters one kind of behavior grows into a large power concentration, this behavior tends to subdue other kinds of behavior, that become invisible or are marginalized. This is what has happened to what we call western culture.
What we have now are large concentrations of power that are outside of any democratic control. They have the tools that enable them to operate: capital and knowledge of the kind of organization that is needed to increase revenue. The interests of heads of corporations are mingled with "common" people and employees through their shareholdings, and with political power through their economic importance and personal contacts, and thus are allowed to operate quite freely. Corporations typically based on one kind of production are increasingly intervening in many different forms of production. They become the generalists, have general knowledge and can work with many different areas while persons are increasingly reduced to only doing one thing. Specialization ensures delivery of productive forces for concentrations of power and consumers of the different things that they produce. In contrast to other ideologies, the profit ideology needs no followers; the specialists are replaceable. It doesn�t need to convince anybody � because the profit ideology addresses the lowest common denominator: basic needs and greed.
Now "life sciences" or biological engineering is probably going to be the largest sector in the U.S. economy. The possibilities to profit from new species, medicines and treatments are enormous. This is widely recognized and is the main reason why there have been almost no obstacles to passing laws on ownership of genetic material. Everybody can see the sound arguments. Why should we stop something that has such a promising future? Patenting life is another example of how legislation not only allows, but actually promotes a behavior that is driven by profit (although there are of course persons who work in this area because they believe that they are helping fight disease and hunger). So far it is resulting in, yes, huge profits and in greater differences between persons apart from the risk of irreversible consequences for life on the planet.
We have a situation where a few people and organizations are legal holders of copyright to genetic information about ourselves and what we eat. Soon, DNA has to pay before it replicates.
As before: ownership, copyright, property laws first and foremost serve to secure the interests of concentrations of power. We have to ask ourselves how we want to contribute to this. What we want to work for and why. What do you want to work for and why? Why are you interested in copyright?

ST:
Why am I interested in copyright? And how do I intend to use my knowledge?
I am fascinated - as well as worried - by the fact that the whole complex of intellectual property rights as we know it today, taking the rights for granted, is a historical invention. In 1710 when the Statute of Anne � the World�s first copyright law � granted 14-year monopolies on literary works to London booksellers, copyright had nothing like the wide-ranging effects of intellectual property rights of our time. During the centuries that have passed between 1710 and today the duration of protection has gone up to the life-time of the author plus 70 years; the scope of subject matter has been widened drastically to include photographs, logarithms, databases, and much more; and copyright - no longer merely a temporary exclusive right to print a work � has become a much more far-reaching bundle of rights: publication rights, adaptation rights, distribution rights, moral rights, etc. The development of copyright law was never an inevitable development. The history of copyright has been determined by many different interests. The rights of authors are not more "adequately" protected today than 300 years ago: authors� rights are simply defined in a different way now.
What I want to know more about is how we got from the Statute of Anne to today�s World Intellectual Property (WIPO) Copyright Treaty? And can copyright in its present form be justified? Does copyright serve the purposes as stated in the WIPO Treaty: "to be an incentive for literary and artistic creation" and "to balance the rights of authors and the larger public interest"?
Many commentators on intellectual property have noted that the general public is relatively unaware of the developments within the law. Professor of intellectual property law David Vaver has remarked that: "There isn�t any ordinary conversation about intellectual property. Those who have no professional reason to be involved with it rarely think about it."7 And Stephen L. Carter has noted further that: "There are calls for the public to become better educated about IP � but such a public would surely demand a greater coherence and persuasiveness from the system than it presently exhibits."8
Copyright law has a great impact upon public life and upon the access to knowledge of individual persons. New inventions, art, writing, and public debate all rely on the usage of material that may be copyright. But people do not know enough about the direction legislators are taking these years. When the EU harmonized the period of protection "upwards" from 50 to 70 years in 1996 how many people realized that this was taking place? And how many know why duration was harmonized "upwards"? Before 1996 only Germany had such a long term - the normal term was 50 years. Legislators apparently found it less offensive to extend the terms of all other countries than to �rip� Germans of their rights. But I think that this choice had unfortunate consequences in countries where works that had come into the public domain were suddenly recopyrighted. In Britain editions of works by for example James Joyce (d.1941), Virginia Woolf (d.1941), and Thomas Hardy (d.1928) prepared for the time when copyright had expired suddenly became impossible. This is one example of the loss the public might suffer without even knowing it. Students may be deprived of new critical editions, the general reading public may have to suffer a bad translation for another twenty years, etc.
I find it important that the public should know the trends of intellectual property law and know that copyright can be a good thing but that too much of it does have severe costs. I would like to assist in the dissemination of knowledge of these matters that have an impact on so many people�s lives.


Notes:

1 Douglas and Others v. Hello! Ltd, The Times, 16 January 2001. The couple was Michael Douglas and Catherine Zeta-Jones. The magazine Hello! had bought paparazzo photos from the couples� wedding. An injunction was granted and later lifted by the English high court with the result that the magazine was able to publish the photos. Douglas and Zeta-Jones then proceeded to trial to obtain damages and won (April 2003).

2 In the second of his Two Treatises on Civil Government (1690) Locke develops his famous labour theory of property. The theory creates the ideological foundation of the Berne Convention and is represented in Article 27 (2) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.

3 Locke, John. The Second Treatise of Civil Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. Edited by J. W. Gough. Blackwell�s Political Texts. Eds. C. H. Wilson and R. B. McCallum. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1948 (1690)., p. 17.

4 Steinberg, Theodore. Slide Mountain, or The Folly of Owning Nature. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995.

5 Donaldon v. Beckett (1774) 2 Bro PC 129; 4 Burr 2408.

6 Alan MacFarlane discusses an ancient difference between Roman and feudal law. Roman law recognises things as property and divisible. Feudal lawyers saw things in themselves as impartible whereas property rights could be divided infinitely. Macfarlane, Alan. �The Mystery of Property.� Property Relations: Sharing, Exclusion, Legitimacy. Ed. C. Hann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

7 David Vaver, �Patently Absurd,� Oxford Today Michaelmas (2000): 21-22, p. 22.

8 Stephen L. Carter, �Does it Matter whether Intellectual Property is Property?,� Chicago-Kent Law Review 68, no. 2 (1993): 715-723, p. 717.


Back to manual for DISCUSSIONS



Back to manuals
Back to HOME