2000 YEARS OF FALLACIES
Peter Zinkernagel interviewed by N55
Peter Zinkernagel, Danish philosopher, 1921-2003. Books:
Doctoral thesis �Omverdensproblemet� 1957 (English version �Conditions
for description� 1962), �Virkelighed� 1989, �Tilvante forestillingers
magt� (�The power of customary views�) in 2001
All the work of Peter Zinkernagel concerns fundamental problems in philosophy.
In his doctoral thesis he formulated certain rules for using language,
conditions for description, repudiating the classical philosophical problem
of the existence of the material world (�how can we know for certain that
there is a world which exists independently of human perception?�) After
the 60s, Zinkernagel was primarily preoccupied with physics while also
formulating the political and ethical consequences of his work on logic.
Based on a conversation recorded in May 1993.
N55:
What is it that you have discovered?
Peter Zinkernagel:
What I have in fact discovered is that thinking is far more difficult
than anyone has ever imagined. Most of our discussions happen on a level
where we repeat and repeat habitual conceptions to each other. But there
exists a level so fundamental that it normally does not appear in our
conscious mind, where things are not about more or less well founded subjective
opinions - here things are simply right or wrong. So far, one has believed
that the formal logic of Aristotle, which is the part of this fundamental
level that was first formulated, was the only place where one could speak
of right and wrong in this way. In formal logic, the presumption is that
one is able to deduce right conclusions from certain basic evaluations,
premises, and that these conclusions are true as long as they do not contradict
themselves.
Thus far, one has believed that formal logic was unconditionally valid,
- one can not contradict oneself - but in addition, it was taken for granted
that it was the only thing that was unconditionally valid, and the only
that was strictly necessary. Philosophy, by concentrating efforts on issues
of language, overlooked that there is a necessary relation between person
and body, and by questioning the material reality, it overlooked the fact
that persons have bodies that exist in the same reality, more precisely
in concrete situations. And that every assertion is necessarily about
reality. Had it been presumed that the assertions made within formal logic
are conditioned by necessary relations between different factors, for
example that an assertion only exists through the force of a certain relation
between an assertion and asserting it and denying it, and that if one
tries both asserting and denying the same assertion, then there is no
assertion - if one had seen these relations, one would also have had to
assume that other necessary relations existed - since one would have no
reason to assume the opposite. But one did not see them; one obviously
believed that what logic is, had now been discovered. Logic was formal
logic
My definition of logic is that logic is necessary relations between different
factors, and factors are that which exist by the force of those relations.
Formal logic is only one example, and by all probability, many exist which
we do not know of. The decisive thing about logical relations is that
they cannot be reasoned. Nevertheless, they constitute necessary conditions
for any description, since they also cannot be denied. The only way to
discover these logical relations is by concentrating on that which is
constantly taken for granted. But from a traditional philosophical point
of view, this is unsubstantiated assertions and tautologies. Still one
must presume that any horse trader in Greece knew that he shouldn�t claim
that a horse was good and at the same time that it wasn�t if he wanted
to convince a customer, and Aristotle only made this knowledge explicit
in a formal system. There are necessary relations between assertions and
what they are assertions about, between assertions and persons, persons
and bodies, bodies and concrete situations. These relations limit and
condition our possibilities of description, and if we forget them, we
do no longer know what we are talking about. If we remove the relation
to the body, we don� t know what we are talking about when we are talking
about persons, and still a body is not the same as a person. And this
we can by no means deduce from formal logic.
Logic is something more fundamental than language. Logic is, for example,
the circumstance that the ashtray on the table prevents me from sliding
my hand over the place where the ashtray is. Material things are first
and foremost characterised by the fact that they limit our actions in
certain ways. We are used to concentrating on the sensual properties of
things - many of our conceptions are connected to the ways in which we
sense the world. For all who are not blind, visual impressions play a
dominant role. Here, our concepts correspond to formal logic; we cannot
imagine that something happens and does not happen, is there and is not.
The elementary logical conditions I am directing attention at are often
in opposition to the way we experience the world, because we don�t experience
the world as composed of relations between different factors which only
exist because of these relations, but rather as composed of houses and
people, suns and stars. Children learn what I call logical-practical usage
of language by using words in certain ways relating to the things they
experience through their senses, but at the same time they are not made
conscious of the reasons that these words can be used, and the relations
that condition their own existence. Nobody is concerned with them. And
therefore they are very difficult to grasp. Logical-practical usage of
language, which is what is most often used in daily life, in a strange
way encloses us in language, often to such a degree that we forget that
there are other ways of describing things, for example, by religious or
poetic use of language. When children learn to use language, they also
learn how to keep from experiencing the world in a non-verbal way, with
a sort of comprehensiveness. But as soon as one gets in touch with logical
relations, the frames of what we normally refer to as thinking, then it
becomes clear that if one tries to deny them, we get pure babble. Then,
what we normally understand by language disappears. If one starts talking
of persons without bodies, one can say anything, and therefore there is
nothing that is worth saying. Furthermore, if one can no longer talk of
assertions as something that is made by persons, then what could we possibly
understand by assertions? And can you refer to a person which is not in
a concrete situation? Descartes� well-known division of persons into a
"thinking thing" and an "extended thing" is really
hopeless, but he makes one wonderful remark: "Although people often
complain that they are not as rich or skilful as others, they still feel
that they are in possession of a healthy ability to reason - the Lord
obviously succeeded in distributing that ability evenly". It is a
rare thing to hear people complain that they do not have common sense.
The decisive, elementary things are completely common for all, the prime
minister and the worker, and all other differences that may exist between
persons are completely irrelevant in relation to this basic level - it
is so basic that everybody, even if they are not conscious about it, uses
it when they talk.
One could also say that I have discovered a very fundamental natural law.
It is quite serious that not even physicists have discovered what a natural
law is - but if one doesn�t accept my definition of logic, it becomes
impossible to even say what a natural law is! According to this definition,
a natural law is a necessary quantitative relation between different factors,
in contrast to the customary definition of logic, where a natural law
is an empirical regularity, and thus something that could be different
tomorrow. This customary logic offers a very insufficient understanding
of what it is we deal with in physics. Presumably, no physicist doubts
that the sun rises tomorrow, but they are unable to prove their conviction.
If one only accepts formal logic, one gets a serious contradiction between
what one theoretically has to accept - that the sun perhaps will not rise
tomorrow- and what one of course believes in practicality - that it will
rise. That it will rise, one is unable to explain, because one, per definition,
has abolished all other necessary relations than those of formal logic.
One overlooks the condition for description that our very existence is
determined by physical conditions. We were walking on earth also before
Newton discovered the law of gravity.
Even after the theory of relativity, physicists experience space and time
as containers where the physical bodies exist and where the physical processes
are played out. But the decisive things in recent physics imply that space/time
act as proper physical quantities in line with mass, energy etc
Now, afterwards, one can see, if I am right, that if one makes only one
necessary assumption, one can directly deduce the special theory of relativity,
and it becomes almost obvious what quantum mechanics is. Physically, velocity
exists only because of a relation to mass density. [Mass density is the
mass in a point: The mass of a body divided by its extension assumes a
certain limiting value - the mass density.] But in classical mechanics,
the assumption is that we operate with constant mass densities, mass densities
that remain unaffected by the velocity of the body. According to the theory
of relativity, the velocity of a body cannot exceed the speed of light,
which is introduced as a constant, and if the body is still being affected,
instead of increased velocity, its mass density will increase
Classical mechanics operate with constant mass densities, which presuppose
absolutely rigid bodies, meaning bodies whose different points cannot
be moved independently of each other. Now the point is that there are
no absolutely rigid bodies, only bodies with varying degrees of elasticity.
This is decisive for the theory of relativity, because in the space/time-description
here, mass densities increase with velocity and bodies are therefore shortened
in the direction of movement. This deformation is only unambiguous if
one looks away from the deformation that is caused by the elasticity of
the bodies. In order to avoid this ambiguity in the theory, one must therefore
treat almost rigid bodies as if they were absolutely stiff bodies
This [assumption, that mass densities do not depend on velocity] leads
to an inconsistency, since this means that there exists no relation between
the mass on the one hand and space/time on the other. And if we say that
we by a natural law, understand a necessary quantitative relation between
different factors - and by physical quantities we understand quantities
that are part of such relations - then space and time and mass are not
physical quantities because they are not part of quantitative relations
with each other. When constant mass densities lead to the conclusion that
there exist no such relation between mass and dynamic quantities on the
one hand and space/time/matter on the other, meaning they are independent
from velocity, then the simplest way of changing this is to assume that
they are depending on velocity. It thereby also becomes clear that space
and time are physical quantities and not human forms of perception such
as Kant believed them to be.
Now if one begins with the necessary assumption that mass densities are
dependent on velocity, meaning that one accepts that there is a relation
between mass and dynamic quantities on the one hand and space/time/matter
on the other, it becomes clear that space and time are proper physical
quantities that form part of necessary quantitative relations with mass
and energy. But this is only valid when almost rigid bodies are treated
as if they were absolutely rigid bodies. Therefore, classical-relativistic
space-time has a limited area of validity, which also shows in the description
of the quantum-mechanic systems. The space-time used here is characterised
by that we are talking of probability densities, not mass densities, and
by that the relation between dynamic and space-time quantities is broken:
we can know the position of an electron, but then not its impulse, or
its impulse, but then not its position
Another example is that we can not refer to points and distances independently
of each other, because we by points understand something which is characterised
by their distance to other points, and distances we understand as distances
between points. Points and distances are totally different quantities,
but still we cannot refer to either without referring to the other. As
soon as one becomes conscious of these relations, one�s understanding
of physics becomes far better. At the same time, physics is far more difficult
than we believe - the reason why it is experienced as fairly simple is
again habitual thinking, and all the possibilities we look away from.
It is far from simple. The decisive thing is that we get, if I am right,
a better physics. And that presumably becomes of practical importance.
I can point at experiments that would come up with other results than
one normally counts on. There are excellent criteria for deciding that
one theory is better than the other, and that satisfies my assertions.
One of the necessary relations exists between persons and rights. If one
says that persons, or certain persons, ought not to have rights, one signs
away the use of the word ought. It has been assumed, again in formal logic,
that it is impossible to deduct an ought to-sentence from a that-sentence
- that it is impossible to conclude from the statement that something
is, to the claim that it ought to be different. I mean quite literally
that all we know about politics is that politics ought to respect the
rights of persons. Unless one agrees upon the normative foundation of
the political efforts, such as that politics ought to respect the rights
of persons, political discussions become meaningless. If people disagree
about what to emphasize, it becomes impossible to talk of preferring one
alternative to another. Norms that are regarded as given is the precondition
of any political discussion. Any discussion of values presupposes common
norms, and by norms we must understand something that we cannot disagree
about without having to redefine what norms are. Conditions of power have
for tens of thousands of years been closely connected with the idea of
growth as an absolute good. It was absolutely good to have more of what
was good. Now we are in a radically different situation, but the European
Union (EU) and prevailing economical thinking still are based upon these
hopelessly outdated values. We can by no means afford to think in that
way any longer. The debate around the EU in Denmark has to a far too high
extent been characterised by details, advantages and disadvantages concerning
a closer cooperation. Nobody is capable of foreseeing the advantages of
a political and economical union. The pro-EU campaigners claim that they
are in favor of increased cooperation, and thereby they tone down the
fact that what we are really talking about is an increased power concentration.
As long as one keeps talking of the details, then of course people get
confused. And what should be discussed is one thing and only one thing:
Should we concentrate power further? This aspect is subdued and is blurred
together with a lot of other things which are clear to no one. Power is
characterised by always being in opposition to other powers. And according
to all our experiences: it renders us powerless.
If we accept that the only thing we know about politics is that it should
respect the rights of persons and that we should try to organise the smallest
concentrations of power possible, no one can predict the possibilities
that might unfold, since we thereby would change the foundations of our
evaluations, again leading to a change in what is conceived as politically
possible. The same instance as it becomes clear to the population that
power must be limited, the options for organization and collaboration
will also automatically change.
It can be argued that this is remote and unrealistic idealism - there
are no other arguments - but what are today regarded as political realities
are things that are based on other ideals, such as that power is the real
reality, we are all subjugated to mechanisms of power, this is the way
we are; and thereby one overlooks the fact that a change in the basic
valuations is the important thing. All I am doing is directing attention
at something that everybody is capable of understanding: the difference
between respecting power, and the opposite. You don�t have to be a professor
to be able to see that. If everybody realizes this, nobody knows what
will happen, because we have no precedents. We would know what the task
was about - to reduce concentrations of power as much as possible - and
no one would know how. Thus far all we have known has been based on other
concepts, for example, that we knew what was politically possible - that
is what is understood by political realities - and it is precisely those
that are so complex and impossible to grasp. Hopefully, by making these
totally banal circumstances explicit, we can increase consciousness about
necessary norms for politics and become able to concentrate on the real
task - to realize these norms. It is decisive. If we abolish reality and
personal morals, we abolish ourselves.
Our daily lives are quite literally decided by international corporations.
Via the commercials and via consumerism, our lives are decided by the
struggle between different forms of power, in spite of the seeming freedom
we live with. Theoretically, it is possible to step outside of society,
but it poses very serious demands on the individual. The choices of the
individual in a certain sense do not exist, he or she nearly has to take
part in the attempt to acquire as many consumer goods as possible, that
is the way things work. This is a very subtle form of power, you don�t
even have to openly kill someone; you can just let the corporations do
the fighting.
Back to manual for DISCUSSIONS
Back to manuals
Back to HOME
|